Apologies for the long silence on this blog! I’ve been distracted for the past month with other things. I’m taking several interesting math classes this semester, one of which I have been liveTeXing and one of which has (at least for now) been providing notes. I’ve also been taking the Kan seminar at MIT. I recently gave a half-hour talk for that class, on Segal’s paper “Categories and cohomology theories;” as a short talk, it focused mostly on the key definitions in the paper rather than the proofs. (Reading Gian-Carlo Rota’s book has convinced me that’s not a bad thing.) This post contains the notes for that talk.
The goal of this talk is to motivate the notion of “homotopy coherence,” and in particular the example of (special) -spaces. In particular, the goal is to find a “homotopy coherent” substitute for the notion of a topological abelian monoid.
Why might we want such a notion? Given a topological abelian monoid , one can form the classifying space
, which still acquires the structure of a topological abelian monoid (if we use the usual simplicial construction). It follows that we can iterate the construction, producing a sequence of topological abelian monoids
together with maps . If
is a topological abelian group, then these maps are all equivalences, and we have an infinite delooping of
. Therefore, we can extract a cohomology theory from
.
If is not assumed to be a group, then the maps
are still equivalences for
and we get a cohomology theory out of
. This ability to extract an infinite loop space is a very desirable property of topological abelian monoids. Unfortunately, topological abelian monoids are always products of Eilenberg-MacLane spaces, but we’d like to deloop other spaces. Motivated by this, let us take the delooping question as central and declare:
Requirement: A good definition of a “homotopy coherent” topological abelian monoid should have the following properties. If is a homotopy coherent topological monoid, then:
should come with the structure of a homotopy commutative
space.
- We should be able to build a sequence of spaces
and maps
such that if
is grouplike (i.e.,
is a group), then these maps are equivalences (so that we get an infinite delooping of
).
- Conversely, any infinite loop space should be a candidate for
.
- Finally, the definition should not require explicitly assuming a delooping to begin with!
Example 1 The space is a homotopy commutative
space (classifying stable vector bundles). It is not a topological abelian group (otherwise,
-theory would be periodic integral cohomology!), but we want
to be an example of a “homotopy coherent” abelian group as
classifies stable vector bundles, which come with an addition which we would like to believe is “coherently” commutative. In particular,
is an infinite loop space via Bott periodicity
.
We might start by suggesting a commutative monoid in the homotopy category of spaces: that is, a homotopy commutative H space. In other words, it is a space together with a multiplication
and a unit
which satisfy the axioms of a commutative monoid, up to homotopy. Let’s start with this, and see why it is a bad definition.
Bad definition: A “homotopy coherent” topological abelian monoid is a homotopy commutative (and associative) H space.
This is not an adequate definition. For one thing, the data of a homotopy commutative H space is insufficient to run the Milnor construction and to build the classifying space (let alone the iterated classifying spaces).
Example 2 Let . It is a theorem of Adams (in his paper “The sphere considered as an H space mod
“) that the localization
is a homotopy associative, homotopy commutative H space for
, but Adams also shows that for infinitely many
, a topological associative monoid with that mod
homology cannot exist.
A homotopy commutative H space is a space together with a multiplication which is homotopy commutative and associative. In the homotopy coherent setting, we want to keep track of the homotopies which verify commutativity (or associativity) of the product, and we want these homotopies to satisfy higher coherence conditions (which are verified by certain even higher homotopies, which satisfy their own coherence conditions).
Analogy: Recall the notion of a symmetric monoidal category. A symmetric monoidal category comes with a bifunctor
and natural isomorphisms (“homotopies”) describing commutativity and associativity of
, which are part of the data. These relations are required to satisfy coherence conditions (if we were working with higher categories we would have higher coherence homotopies). Segal shows that the notion of a special
-space satisfies the above requirements, and exhibits infinite loop structures on a variety of spaces of interest. It turns out that one can still extract from a special
-space a sequence as in (1).
To motivate the definition of a special -space, let’s recall that an abelian monoid in a category
with products is an object
together with morphisms
and
satisfying various relations. It is awkward to say “satisfying various relations” in a homotopy-theoretic setting. Roughly speaking, for every relation (such as the relation that
is equal to
) we want a homotopy verifying this relation, together with coherence data on these homotopies. Unfortunately, it is awkward to spell out all these coherence homotopies in detail: there are infinitely many of them!
Fortunately, there are other ways of phrasing the definition of an abelian monoid, which do not require explicit relations. Segal uses a “diagrammatic” version of the definition which generalizes naturally to the homotopy setting.
Definition 1 Let be the category of finite sets and partially defined maps. (Given partially defined maps
and
, then the composite morphism
is defined on
.)
Let be an abelian monoid. Then we get a functor
defined as follows:
- If
is a finite set, then
.
- If
is a partially defined map, then we define
by
The above data encodes the entire structure of abelian monoid on . In fact, we can go in the other direction, as well, under certain conditions.
Proposition 2 Any functor
such that for any finite sets
, the map
(arising from the partially defined maps
) is an isomorphism and
, arises as
for a unique abelian monoid
.
In fact, we have an equivalence between abelian monoids and functors which turn coproducts into products. This is true in any category
with finite products. A functor
that turns coproducts into products is the same thing as an abelian monoid object in
. For instance, if
is the category of topological spaces, then a functor
which turns coproducts into products is precisely a topological abelian monoid. We thus get a “diagrammatic” reformulation of the axioms defining a topological abelian monoid.
Definition 3 (Segal) A special -space is a functor
with the property that for finite sets
, the map
is a homotopy equivalence.
In particular, the space acquires the structure of a homotopy commutative H space, as the functor
is product-preserving. Observe that a
-space
is in some sense a type of structure placed on the space
, and we will abuse notation and talk about “
-structures” on a space
(meaning a
-space extending
).
Example 3 Not every product-preserving functor lifts to a functor
: that is, there are homotopy commutative H spaces which are not
-spaces, since not every homotopy commutative groulike H space can be delooped. This provides examples of homotopy commutative diagrams of spaces which cannot be strictified.
Thesis: -spaces are the “correct” homotopy coherent analog of an topological abelian monoid.
One way to “prove” this thesis is to show that -spaces satisfy the requirements. For instance, we should be able to place
-structures on numerous spaces (such as
), and on the other hand we should have enough structure to perform operations such as forming the classifying space and group completion. The following result shows that there is a rich supply of
-spaces arising from symmetric monoidal categories.
Theorem 4 (Segal) Let
be a symmetric monoidal category. Then the nerve (recall that
means to take the subcategory of isomorphisms)
canonically admits the structure of a
-space.
The intuition behind this result is that a -category is really the same thing as a symmetric monoidal category; the notion of a symmetric monoidal category answers the question at the beginning of this post if we were working with categories rather than spaces.
Example 4 Consider the category of finite sets, which is a symmetric monoidal category under the coproduct. The nerve is , which is consequently a
-space (it is essentially the “free”
-space on a point, i.e. it is the “free homotopy algebra”
). In other words, given a
-structure on a space
, to give a map of
-spaces
up to homotopy is equivalent to giving an element of
.
Observe that the composition structure on comes from juxtaposition of permutations
. In fact,
is a strictly associative topological monoid.
Example 5 Let’s now see why is a
-space, or at least half of the reason. Consider thetopological category of finite-dimensional
-vector spaces and isomorphisms. This is a symmetric monoidal (topologically enriched) category under the direct sum. We can make sense of the nerve of a topologically enriched category (it is a geometric realization of a simplicial spacenow), and the above theorem makes sense for such. Observe that we have an equivalence
According to the above result, is a
-space. One can show from this that
is a
-space using the “group completion” theorem.
Finally, let’s sketch the delooping construction. Given a -space
, we would like to extract a sequence of spaces
together with maps which are equivalences for
. If
is a group, then
is an equivalence as well, and we get on
the structure of aninfinite loop space. In order to do this, recall that the classical construction of
for a topological group
is the geometric realization of a simplicial space which looks like
. Segal’s observation is that a
-space provides enough structure to build such a simplicial space, and thus a geometric realization.
Unfortunately, given a -space
, we cannot build a simplicial space from
: the simplicial identities will not be verified. However, we don’t really need
there; we could replace it with something equivalent to it. Segal produces a simplicial space which looks like
where the maps are defined using the combinatorics of .
Definition 5 We define a functor
as follows. Given a finite nonempty totally ordered set
, we send it to
where
is the smallest element. Given a map
of totally ordered sets, we have to define a partially defined map of sets
. We send
to
(which is undefined if no such
exist).
Definition 6 Given a
-space
, we let
be the geometric realization of the associated simplicial space. In fact,
itself acquires the structure of a
-space, assigning to a finite set
the geometric realization of the
-space
. We can thus form
and so forth.
The main result is:
Theorem 7 (Segal) If
is grouplike, then
for all
and
is an infinite loop space. In any event, we have
for
.
What I didn’t have time for in the talk is the stronger result that special -spaces which are grouplike are equivalent (as an
-category) to the
-category
of connective spectra. I’m not sure I yet have a really convincing reason in my mind for why this should be. One possible reason is that there is an equivalence between spectra and excisive functors from finite pointed spaces to spaces (a spectra
defines an excisive functor
), whereas special
-spaces are precisely excisive functors on finite discrete spaces. There has to be a result describing when left Kan extensions of excisive functors are excisive, but I don’t know it. Perhaps someone can help here?
Leave a Reply