I have been planning to say a few words about local cohomology, and I stand by that still–but I got sidestracked.
I would now like to explain an interesting phenomenon that we talked about today in topology class. In algebraic topology, one often considers fiber bundles . The idea of a fiber bundle is to generalize the notion of a product space
. A fiber bundle is, loosely, something that locally looks like the projection from a product
. The reason that we only require it to look locally like a product is, for instance, that we want the tangent bundle to be considered a fiber bundle. However, as is well known, the tangent bundle to a manifold may admit no nonzero global sections—which means that it cannot be trivial. Nonetheless, given a fiber bundle, one may ask in some sense how strongly it fails to be nontrivial.
A detailed study of such questions belongs to the theory of characteristic classes, which I am not currently ready to talk about. Nonetheless, let us start with a very simple question. Let be a fiber bundle over a compact space
. There is then, by definition, an open covering
of
such that the restricted fiber bundles
is trivial, isomorphic to
for
the fiber. Clearly we can take this cover finite. One might naturally ask how small we can take this cover.
We shall describe the answer in a specific important case. One of the standard examples of a fiber bundle is the Hopf bundle
The description is straightforward. An element in can be viewed as an
-tuple of complex numbers. This spans a line through the origin and maps to a point in
. The fiber corresponds to all the points on a circle that span the same fixed complex line, which is traced out by a circle. In fact, this is more than a simple fiber bundle.
Since is a group, this is a principal
-bundle. This has the following consequence. If the bundle admits a section, then it is trivial. This is a general fact about principal bundles, and it is also true locally (i.e. on open sets). Let us now check that this is in fact locally trivial, and in fact find sections locally. Consider the open sets
of points of
represented by homogeneous coordinates
with
.
Given an element , we map this to
. If we divide this by its norm, we get an element of
which maps down to it. So we have sections over the
. So the bundle is trivial over each
, by principalness.
Of course, there is an easier way to see that the bundle is trivial over : namely,
is contractible, and any fiber bundle over a contractible space is trivial. But in any case, we see the claim. In total, we find that there is a covering of the base space
by
open sets on which the Hopf bundle is trivial. Is this the best possible?
Theorem 1 Any trivializing cover of the base
of the Hopf bundle is of size at least
.
The proof is not difficult, but it is ingenious. The first thing to recall is that there is a homological theory of fiber bundles. When one has a product space, one can use the Kunneth formula to calculate the cohomology of a product from that of its components. Under reasonable assumptions, the Kunneth theorem extends to fiber bundles as well; it is called the Leray-Hirsch theorem. This requires cohomology classes on the total space that generate the cohomology of the fiber at each point. But even that fails here because of
is trivial while
is nontrivial. The more powerful general theorem, called the Serre spectral sequence, is still valid here, but we shall not use anything so fancy. So we shall try something else.
Namely, we shall use even more elementary methods. Let be an open cover of
over which the Hopf bundle is trivial. Suppose
. Note that we have a very good understanding of the singular cohomology rings of all these three spaces.
The most interesting of , which can be shown, either by elementary means or even by appealing to the Serre spectrnal sequence (I’ll have to explain this someday), to be
where
is the generating class in degree two. Intuitively, one should think of this as a complex plane.
Consider the element . It pulls back to zero in
as
has no cohomology in degree two. This is actually unexpected. If one has a product map
, the map
is actually injective (if
have, say, finitely generated cohomology) by the Kunneth formula.
In particular, this means that is injective. So the fact that
goes to zero in
means that it goes to zero in
for each
. This in turn implies that
goes to zero in
. By the long exact sequence in cohomology, this means that
comes from an element in
.
Now one of the properties of the cup product is that if is a space and
are open sets, the cup product of classes
is actually in
. The reason is essentially that a homology cycle lying in
can be split into pieces in
and
by the excision property.
Now this means that for each
. In particular, the cup-product of all of them is in
. But if
, we know that
, as it is the generator of
. This is the contradiction. And that completes the proof.
The essential idea of the above proof is to use the algebra structure on the singular cohomology, and in particular the fact that the cohomology ring of projective space is highly nontrivial.
Leave a Reply