I am going to get back shortly to discussing algebraic number theory and discrete valuation rings. But this tidbit from EGA 1 that I just learned today was too much fun to resist. Besides, it puts the material on completions in more context, so I think the digression is justified.
Lifting Idempotents
The theorem says we can lift “approximate idempotents” in complete rings to actual ones. In detail:
Theorem 1 Let
be a ring complete with respect to the
-adic filtration. Then if
is idempotent (i.e.
) then there is an idempotent
such that
reduces to
.
More elegantly, if for a ring
denotes the set of idempotents, we have
surjective.
The proof I knew of earlier is a fairly straightforward application of Hensel’s lemma, that more general result which I plan to cover in the future. But there is a proof using (a very little bit of) algebraic geometry.
The first step is to prove:
Proposition 2 Let
be a ring and
a nilpotent ideal. Then
is surjective.
Indeed, the topological spaces of and
are the same. The result then follows from the next section.
Idempotents and Connectedness
Idempotents measure the disconnectedness of for a ring
:
Proposition 3 If
, then there is a one-to-one correspondence between
and the open and closed subsets of
.
Given an open and closed , we have
. Since
, we can define a global section
of the structure sheaf by
on
,
on
.
Similarly, if is an idempotent, then
must be either
or
for
, because there are no nontrivial idempotents in a local ring. (If
were a nontrivial idempotent in a local ring, then
, and either
or
is necessarily invertible.) So we can set
. It can be checked that
is open, and so is
by symmetry. This establishes the bijection I claimed. (Another approach here is to note that idempotents decompose
as a product
in the category of rings, which corresponds by fully faithful contravariantness the contravariant equivalence of
to a coproduct in the category of affine schemes. Except one has to check that an open and closed subscheme of an affine scheme is itself affine. Perhaps this is easy, but a quick proof wasn’t obvious to me at least.)
So the first proposition is now proved. Finally, we need to prove the theorem. Well, choose an idempotent . Lift it to
, and inductively to
. In the inverse limit, we get an idempotent
reducing to
.
There are some useful applications of this in representation theory, because one can look for idempotents in endomorphism rings; these tell you whether a module can be decomposed as a direct sum into smaller parts. Except, of course, that endomorphism rings aren’t necessarily commutative and this proof breaks down.
Leave a Reply